Unalienated Value: Difference between revisions

From P2P Foundation
Jump to navigation Jump to search
No edit summary
 
(One intermediate revision by the same user not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
'''= "relations of open reciprocity, communal sharing, gift-giving and voluntary collaboration allowed value to circulate in its unalienated forms, including labor power, political expression and interspecies ecological exchanges".''' [http://revistas.ucm.es/index.php/TEKN/article/view/52847/49997]




Line 98: Line 100:




==History of the Concept: Smith and Marx==
==[[Unalienated Value]] and self-generation==
Ron Eglash:
"In  contrast to  Smith’s  claim  that  industrial  capital  offered  a  self-generating  source  of  value, Marx  focused  on  labor  and  nature  as  the  only  components  that  are  truly  self-generating1. Some  of  his  best  examples are  the  indigenous  societies  described  in  his Ethnological Note-books.  Drawing on Lewis Morgan’s  work with the Iroquois and other early anthropologists, Marx  noted  that  in  these  indigenous  societies  the  labor  that  goes  into  growing  a  bushel  of corn  or  crafting a knife  is  visible rather  than  hidden,  and relations  of  reciprocity,  communal sharing,  and  gift-giving,  rather  than  cold  blooded  calculation,  allowed  that  labor  value  to circulate  in  an  unalienated  form  (Graeber,  2012).  While  not  all  indigenous  societies  were egalitarian,  examples  such  as the Iroquois, who had a  rich  structure  for democratic decision-making--establishing  women’s  voting  rights  500  years  before  any  European nation  did so—were  ample  evidence that  without  the wealth  inequality  created  by  capitalism, deep  political equality  would  be  possible.From  the  viewpoint of Adam  Smith,  the economic  value  of a  commodity  is the  revenue you  get  by  selling  it,  so  it  is  only  common  sense  that  the  owner  of a  factory  owns  all  its profits.  For  Marx the owner  of  the factory is extracting  value  from the  labor  that  generated it, and unethically  hoarding  that  value  in the  form of profits. Workers  are  complacent  in  part because  the  monetary  system of banks  and  bills  makes the hording  invisible:  I don’t see my boss putting a thousand ears of corn in his wallet, while only 10 ears go into mine. But they are  also  complacent  because  replacing  the  experience  of  artisanal  production—pride  in crafting,  contributing  and  communing  with  tools,  users  and  resources—with  the  mind numbing  alienation  of  mass  production  drastically  changes  one’s  perspective:  consumption becomes  the  only  form  of  identity,  and  social,  cultural  and  political  structures  begin  to  re-flect  the consumer  mentality.
In  addition  to unalienated  labor  value,  Marx eventually  noted  the importance  of  unalien-ated ecological  value.  In  earlier  writing  (letter of January 7, 1851) he scoffed at the need for environmental  protection  because  of  “the  progress  of  science  and  industry.”  But  by  the 1860s, inspired  by  the  new soil  chemistry  studies of Justus von Liebig  (Foster  and  Magdoff, 2011),  he  critiqued  capitalist  agriculture  for  the  way  it  “disturbs  the  metabolic  interaction between  man  and  the  earth, i.e.  it  prevents  the  return  to  the soil  of  its  constituent  elements consumed  by  man in  the  form of  food  and clothing...All  progress  in capitalist  agriculture is a progress  in  the  art, not only of robbing  the  worker, but  of  robbing  the  soil...” (Marx 1976, pp.  637-638).Although  not  emphasized  as  much  as  labor  and  nature,  Marx  also  mapped  out  a  third form  which  I  will  refer to  as  “expressive”  value.  In the Grundrisse,  he  predicted  that  tech-nological  improvements  under  communism  would  create  so  much  wealth  that  workers would  have  abundant  free  time  in  the  form  of  unalienated  intellectual  pursuits,  arts,  recre-ation,  and  other  creative  and  emotional  expressions.  As  a  practicing  journalist  for  most  of his  career  (publishing  362  articles  in The New York Tribune  alone),  Marx  also  highlighted expressive  value  in media:  “The  free press  is  the ubiquitous  vigilant eye  of  a people's  soul, the embodiment  of  a  people's  faith  in  itself” (Marx, 1842)
...
With  these  three  pillars  of  unalienated  labor,  ecological,  and  expressive  value,  one can  un-derstand  the  optimism of  the  1917  revolution in  what  would  become the  USSR.  It’s  hard  to imagine  a more  horrifyingly  failed  vision.  Rather than  return  people  to  the  egalitarian  rela-tions  of  indigenous  societies,  the  USSR  was  marked  by  widespread  poverty,  income inequality, environmental  degradation, rampant  militarism and  a  human  rights  record so  bad that  new  terms  like  “Orwellian”  had  to  be  created  for  it.  Davies  (1998) for  example  notes that  the  death  toll  due  to  Stalin-era  economic  policies  has  been  estimated  at  10  million. Even  with  “cost  savings”  measures  such  as  forced  labor  camps,  about  30  million  (one  of every  8  citizens) were still  living in poverty  by  the dissolution  in  1990  (Slay,  2009). Where did Marxist  analysis  go  wrong?In  all  three  domains  Marx  demonstrated  the  advantages  of  unalienated  forms.  But  his model  of  communism  could  not  accommodate  the  very  phenomena  he  used  to  justify  it. Figure  2  shows  the  flow of value  under  communism: as  in  the  case of Adam Smith’s capit-alist  system, it  communism  required  that  value  must be extracted.  In part that  was  required by centralization,  which  Marx saw as the only means  to  redistribute  value.  His 1848 Mani-festo of the Communist Party calls for  strict  centralization of “all instruments  of  production” (factories,  machines,  agricultural  estates,  mines,  etc.)  as  well  as  finances,  communication, transportation,  and  even  the  workforce--an  “industrial  army”--in  the  hands  of  the  state (1974,  pp.  86-87).  But  equally  important  was  Marx’s  conviction  that  the  unalienated  labor of  traditional  cultures  was  simply  too  inefficient.  Providing  barely  enough  for  subsistence; it  could  not rise beyond  “nature’s  paltriness”  (Natur-bedurftigkeit).  Capitalism was a  neces-sary  stage  before communism  because  it could  condense  the labor  value  of past  generations into  increasingly  efficient  technologies.It  was this  requirement  of  extraction,  and  its  corollary of  centralized  redistribution,  that created  the  ideology  and methods at  the  heart  of the USSR disasters.  Labor  value extraction turned out to be as alienating under  communism  as  it  was under capitalism.  Nature’s  contri-bution  to  the  generation  of  value  was  similarly  betrayed:  plants  came  out  of  farms,  but organic  waste  was  not brought back  to  the soil. Artificial phosphorus  additives  in the  USSR became  so  high  that  following  its  dissolution  in  1990,  world  phosphorus  consumption dropped for a decade  (MIT, 2011)."
(https://www.researchgate.net/publication/304670572_Of_Marx_and_Makers_an_Historical_Perspective_on_Generative_Justice)


=More Information=
=More Information=

Latest revision as of 07:38, 5 March 2017

= "relations of open reciprocity, communal sharing, gift-giving and voluntary collaboration allowed value to circulate in its unalienated forms, including labor power, political expression and interspecies ecological exchanges". [1]


Description

Ron Eglash:

"Marx proposed that capitalism’s destructive force is caused, at root, by the alienation of labor value from its generators. Environmentalists have added the concept of unalienated ecological value, and rights activists added the unalienated expressive value of free speech, sexuality, spirituality, etc. Marx’s vision for restoring an unalienated world by top-down economic governance was never fulfilled. But in the last 30 years, new forms of social justice have emerged that operate as “bottom-up”. Peer-to-peer production such as open source software or wikipedia has challenged the corporate grip on IP in a “gift exchange” of labor value; community based agroecology establishes a kind of gift exchange with our nonhuman allies in nature. DIY citizenship from feminist makerspaces to queer biohacking has profound implications for a new materialism of the “knowledge commons”; and restorative approaches to civil rights can challenge the prison-industrial complex. In contrast to top-down “distributive justice,” all of the above are cases of bottom-up or “generative justice”." (http://revistas.ucm.es/index.php/TEKN/article/view/52847/49997)


Typology

Ron Eglash:

1) Unalienated labor value -- as Marx notes, when labor is alienated from its products, the work becomes meaningless. That is why Barrington-Leigh's examples of open source, where coders often work on passion projects, is so important.

2) Unalienated ecological value -- extracting value from soil, and returning chemicals, is like extracting labor value from workers and returning money. Chemical "amendments" destroy soil ecosystems like consumerism destroys communities.

3) Unalienated expressive value -- free speech, authentic identity around sexuality, spirituality etc., has to feed from the same well springs, and vice-versa.


Discussion

Generating unalienated value

Ron Eglash:

"In Marx’s original formulation of “alienated labor value”, he contrasted the meaningful work of traditional skilled artisans, taking pleasure in their craft and earning respect from their community, with the dull repetition, low pay and enervating conditions of factory labor under capitalism. There are at least four challenges to making the alienation concept useful today. First, corporate marketing schemes are increasingly appropriating the artisanal allure: my Starbucks coffee is served by an underpaid “barista”; my cookies claim they were hand-made by Keebler elves. I can buy Domino’s Artisan Pizzas, Tostitos’ Artisan Recipes Tortilla Chips, Burger King’s Artisan bun, and Dunkin’ Donuts’ Artisan Bagels. If artisanal labor is so easily simulated, what chance do we have for making it a basis of social critique? Second, evoking older, pre-capitalist forms could be read to imply that artisanal labor is better because it is more natural. But as I will outline below, some of the best examples of unalienated craft labor today are in highly “unnatural” realms of open source hardware and software. And romantic organicist notions of what constitutes “natural” labor are notoriously tied to stereotype gender roles; homophobic claims that only heterosexuality is natural; nationalist claims that “nature did not intend the races to mix” and so on. Third, older production forms may be a poor fit to contemporary population densities and needs. And finally, the stress on artisanal production often overlooks the gender, race and ecological dimensions of economies of care and histories of colonialism. To address these problems, we need a deeper look at what the concept of “generating unalienated value” could mean if liberated from some of this unwelcomed baggage.

The phrase “generating value” is implicitly referring to the power of “self-generation.” In his 1944 book What is Life? physicist Erwin Schrödinger noted the mysterious way organisms seemed to defy the second law of thermodynamics: “It is by avoiding the rapid decay into the inert state of 'equilibrium' that an organism appears so enigmatic; so much so, that from the earliest times of human thought some special non-physical or supernatural force... was claimed to be operative” (p. 70). He characterized this self-generative property of life as “negative entropy” (later shortened to “negentropy”). Terms for this phenomenon can now be found at every scale: “autocatalysis” for cycles in which biomolecules produced themselves; “autopoiesis” for an organism’s self-reproduction; “sympoiesis” for ecosystem self-assembly, and so on. When we grow living organisms for food, we tap into this self-generating power; that is to say, some of the value that is normally circulated can be diverted for our own use. It is here that we must choose between either becoming part of the circulation, or extracting— i.e. alienating—that value. Soils for example can be easily depleted of nutrients. Yet traditional farmers and horticulturalists have avoided this problem for thousands of years simply by returning our waste to the soil, and thus becoming part of the circulation of value through a broader array of sustainable practices called agroecology.

Marx made an analogy between unalienated labor and agroecology in Capital volume 1, where he stated that capitalist farming “prevents the return to the soil of its constituent elements consumed by man in the form of food and clothing... All progress in capitalist agriculture is a progress in the art, not only of robbing the worker, but of robbing the soil...” (Marx 1976, pp. 637-638). Recalling Schrödinger’s comment that the negentropic character of life is often attributed to a supernatural force, it is no surprise that Marx’s inspiration for this insight, German chemist Justus von Liebig, originally justified recycling sewage back to farm lands because of a “vital force” that gave living soils their generative power. Marx was dedicated to eliminating “mystification”, but when he invokes the “living labor” of unalienated production, it sounds suspiciously like the vitalist “living soil” of von Liebig. This is not necessarily a flaw. Granted, it does pose the dangers of any organicist or naturalizing discourse, as noted above. But one can also interpret vitalism as humility; as a way of saying “there is something complex and wonderful in the generative force that we do not fully understand”. Indeed that was Schrödinger’s final conclusion. Today we know that the “living soil” concept was not far off: ordinary dirt is a complex ecosystem of bacteria, fungi, nematodes, decaying matter, water percolation, minerals and other features that form a dynamic, evolving network which still challenges our understanding. Analogous complex, selfsustaining networks in the social domain—not the simulation of artisanal labor in the Starbucks barista or Keebler elf—are necessary for real unalienated labor. We will now turn to one exemplar for such a network. " (http://revistas.ucm.es/index.php/TEKN/article/view/52847/49997)


History of the Concept: Smith and Marx

Unalienated Value and self-generation

Ron Eglash:

"In contrast to Smith’s claim that industrial capital offered a self-generating source of value, Marx focused on labor and nature as the only components that are truly self-generating1. Some of his best examples are the indigenous societies described in his Ethnological Note-books. Drawing on Lewis Morgan’s work with the Iroquois and other early anthropologists, Marx noted that in these indigenous societies the labor that goes into growing a bushel of corn or crafting a knife is visible rather than hidden, and relations of reciprocity, communal sharing, and gift-giving, rather than cold blooded calculation, allowed that labor value to circulate in an unalienated form (Graeber, 2012). While not all indigenous societies were egalitarian, examples such as the Iroquois, who had a rich structure for democratic decision-making--establishing women’s voting rights 500 years before any European nation did so—were ample evidence that without the wealth inequality created by capitalism, deep political equality would be possible.From the viewpoint of Adam Smith, the economic value of a commodity is the revenue you get by selling it, so it is only common sense that the owner of a factory owns all its profits. For Marx the owner of the factory is extracting value from the labor that generated it, and unethically hoarding that value in the form of profits. Workers are complacent in part because the monetary system of banks and bills makes the hording invisible: I don’t see my boss putting a thousand ears of corn in his wallet, while only 10 ears go into mine. But they are also complacent because replacing the experience of artisanal production—pride in crafting, contributing and communing with tools, users and resources—with the mind numbing alienation of mass production drastically changes one’s perspective: consumption becomes the only form of identity, and social, cultural and political structures begin to re-flect the consumer mentality.

In addition to unalienated labor value, Marx eventually noted the importance of unalien-ated ecological value. In earlier writing (letter of January 7, 1851) he scoffed at the need for environmental protection because of “the progress of science and industry.” But by the 1860s, inspired by the new soil chemistry studies of Justus von Liebig (Foster and Magdoff, 2011), he critiqued capitalist agriculture for the way it “disturbs the metabolic interaction between man and the earth, i.e. it prevents the return to the soil of its constituent elements consumed by man in the form of food and clothing...All progress in capitalist agriculture is a progress in the art, not only of robbing the worker, but of robbing the soil...” (Marx 1976, pp. 637-638).Although not emphasized as much as labor and nature, Marx also mapped out a third form which I will refer to as “expressive” value. In the Grundrisse, he predicted that tech-nological improvements under communism would create so much wealth that workers would have abundant free time in the form of unalienated intellectual pursuits, arts, recre-ation, and other creative and emotional expressions. As a practicing journalist for most of his career (publishing 362 articles in The New York Tribune alone), Marx also highlighted expressive value in media: “The free press is the ubiquitous vigilant eye of a people's soul, the embodiment of a people's faith in itself” (Marx, 1842)

...

With these three pillars of unalienated labor, ecological, and expressive value, one can un-derstand the optimism of the 1917 revolution in what would become the USSR. It’s hard to imagine a more horrifyingly failed vision. Rather than return people to the egalitarian rela-tions of indigenous societies, the USSR was marked by widespread poverty, income inequality, environmental degradation, rampant militarism and a human rights record so bad that new terms like “Orwellian” had to be created for it. Davies (1998) for example notes that the death toll due to Stalin-era economic policies has been estimated at 10 million. Even with “cost savings” measures such as forced labor camps, about 30 million (one of every 8 citizens) were still living in poverty by the dissolution in 1990 (Slay, 2009). Where did Marxist analysis go wrong?In all three domains Marx demonstrated the advantages of unalienated forms. But his model of communism could not accommodate the very phenomena he used to justify it. Figure 2 shows the flow of value under communism: as in the case of Adam Smith’s capit-alist system, it communism required that value must be extracted. In part that was required by centralization, which Marx saw as the only means to redistribute value. His 1848 Mani-festo of the Communist Party calls for strict centralization of “all instruments of production” (factories, machines, agricultural estates, mines, etc.) as well as finances, communication, transportation, and even the workforce--an “industrial army”--in the hands of the state (1974, pp. 86-87). But equally important was Marx’s conviction that the unalienated labor of traditional cultures was simply too inefficient. Providing barely enough for subsistence; it could not rise beyond “nature’s paltriness” (Natur-bedurftigkeit). Capitalism was a neces-sary stage before communism because it could condense the labor value of past generations into increasingly efficient technologies.It was this requirement of extraction, and its corollary of centralized redistribution, that created the ideology and methods at the heart of the USSR disasters. Labor value extraction turned out to be as alienating under communism as it was under capitalism. Nature’s contri-bution to the generation of value was similarly betrayed: plants came out of farms, but organic waste was not brought back to the soil. Artificial phosphorus additives in the USSR became so high that following its dissolution in 1990, world phosphorus consumption dropped for a decade (MIT, 2011)." (https://www.researchgate.net/publication/304670572_Of_Marx_and_Makers_an_Historical_Perspective_on_Generative_Justice)

More Information

  • Ron Eglash: "This is explained in depth in our publications: www.generativejustice.wikispaces.com/home. Practical implementations are discussed here: www.generativejustice.wikispaces.com/Projects."